Modernity,
Postmodernity, and Family and Consumer
Sciences
Edith
E. Baldwin
Dr. Baldwin lives
in Aireys Inlet, Victoria, Australia. Today
there are so many "voices" screeching
about Reason. Why is there a rage against
Reason? What precisely is being attacked,
criticized, and damned? Why is it that when
"reason" and "rationality"
are mentioned, they evoke images of domination,
oppression, patriarchy, sterility, violence,
totality, totalitarianism, and even terror?
These questions are especially poignant and
perplexing when we realize that not so long ago
the call to "reason" elicited
associations with autonomy, freedom, justice,
equality, happiness, and peace. (Bernstein,
1991, pp. 32-33)
The mode of
rationality dominating the period in history
known as modernity strongly
influenced the profession of home economics as
it emerged and developed (Brown, 1985, 1993). In
recent decades postmodern challenges
to the invasion of social, cultural, and
personal life by instrumental, strategic, and
systems rationality have arisen not only in the
field of home economics/family and consumer
sciences but in philosophy, the social and
physical sciences, politics, and the arts.
So widespread has
been the debate that postmodernity
has become a household word (Lash, 1990). The
term has been discussed in newspaper editorials,
television programs, and popular magazines.
Numerous books and articles in academic journals
have been devoted to the idea of postmodernity
and the questions it raises. We have not only
postmodern thinking expressed in the various
disciplines but the postmodern family
(Stacey, 1996), postmodern education (Doll, 1993;
Elkind,
1997; McLaren, 1991; Mourad, 1997),
and a "postmodern perspective on home
economics history" (Richards, 2000).
Although some writers simply accept
postmodernity as inevitable or as "the way
things are," others are critical of what
are considered to be postmodern trends, values,
and ideas; e.g., in discussing the concept of
theory, Brown and Baldwin (1995) argue for
dialectical theory rather than the adoption of a
postmodern approach that would unreflectively
accept various (and sometimes conflicting)
theories to generate knowledge for the field.
The modernity/postmodernity
debate raises some thought-provoking questions
for family and consumer sciences. This paper
will sketch ideas relating to modernity
and postmodernity to highlight their
significance for family and consumer sciences.
An attempt will be made to show how (a) on one
hand, modernity's conceptions of rationality and
progress in human affairs led to serious
problems for the field and how (b) on the other
hand, adherence to postmodern concepts including
the fundamental idea of difference
would reinforce misunderstandings and
inadequacies. It will then be argued that (c)
family and consumer sciences could go forward
with greater strength through acceptance of the
contemporary notion of modernity as an
unfinished project.
Modernity and
Its Ambiguity
The term modern was first employed in the
late fifth century to distinguish between the
official Christian present and the pagan Roman
past (Habermas, 1997). Since then, it has been
used a number of times to mark a shift from an
old to a new era. It was the Age of Reason in
the second half of the eighteenth century with
the idea of progress elaborated by Kant, Turgot,
Condorcet, and others that gave rise to
modernity. The French Revolution in
1789--revolution based on reason--both expressed
and gave momentum to this new
consciousness, and the Industrial
Revolution provided its material substance
(Kumar, 1995). This modern world, this new
social order, was characterized by a new
dynamism, a rejection of earlier traditions, a
belief in progress, and the potential of human
reason to promote freedom. Increasing
rationality would enhance social understanding,
order and control, justice, moral progress, and
human happiness.
Modernity
stimulated a continual revolution of ideas and
institutions and the continual creation of new
things. The causes and consequences of modernity
are cultural and social; but as Lyon (1999, p.
28) points out, the driving force is
"capitalism with its constant quest for new
raw materials, new sources of labor power . . .
new technologies . . . and new applications that
might attract new consumers." From the
outset modernity promised to change the world in
the name of Reason and each innovation spawned
another.
Modernity's
Achievements
The achievements
of modernity are amazing when we consider how
the world has been irreversibly transformed. Our
mental imagery of modernity is strongly
influenced by the technological and cultural
fruits of industrial civilization, so evident in
great modern cities such as New York and Chicago, e.g., modern
architecture; systems of
transportation and communication; new technology
in medical institutions; representations of
modern culture in theatres, cinemas, and art
galleries (Lyon, 1999). By the 1970s the concept
of modernity had become closely associated with
the United States. Although countless
achievements of modernity surround us in
everyday life, to grasp something of the
controversy accompanying their evolution, we
turn very briefly to the work of major
theorists.
Early
Critics of Modernity
At the beginning
of the twentieth century, Weber was pessimistic
about the application of rationalization
to the social as well as the natural world. The
rational approach underpinning science (i.e.,
empirical science) was systematically infusing
every area of society--not only undermining
tradition but developing a calculating
attitude toward life. Evidence could be found
not only in the science laboratory but in the
capitalist's ledger and in the rules and
hierarchy of bureaucratic organization
emphasizing efficiency and productivity.
He saw dissolution of ethical and personal
relations. Weber warned, "[s]cience in the
name of 'intellectual integrity,' has come
forward with the claim of representing the only
possible form of a reasoned view of the
world" (1970, p. 355); yet technical
rationality produced an "iron cage" of
domination that threatened unity, freedom, and meaning.
Scientific rationality was unable to teach
anything about the meaning of the world, of
human existence; and the continual pursuit of
innovation associated with modernity merely
created restlessness and discontent.
For Marx,
paradoxes were clearly evident, e.g., material
progress accompanied by spiritual
impoverishment, development of scientific
knowledge yet mass ignorance, and conquest of nature
but exploitation of workers (Kumar, 1995).
Although Marx welcomed modernity, he was opposed
to capitalism that brought constant
technological change, a quest for market
dominance, and with it increasing globalization
of a system designed to create profit for some
through exploitation of others. He saw, in these
tendencies, a wedge being driven between
capitalist and worker and between workers
themselves as they competed for jobs. Workers
were exploited and alienated by
capitalism.
In the late
nineteenth and early twentieth century, Durkheim
was concerned about the emergence of anomie
and loss of direction (Lyon, 1999). As
workers migrated from villages and farms to
industrial cities they experienced not only
subdivision of labor and responsibilities but the destruction of traditional ties of
family and neighborhood. This new mobility
uprooted tradition so that rules once governing
life in the village community were replaced by
new rules relating to factory life and
bureaucratic organization. Questions of
authority and identity were raised as tasks once
performed by the family or church were taken
over by schools, youth clubs, welfare groups,
and so on. Durkheim feared that isolation of the
individual and dissolution of social norms would
lead to a sense of uncertainly and loss of
direction. Moreover, with the collapse of the
moral order, pathological anomie might evolve to
the point of suicide (Lyon).
To some, the great
modern cities brought the problem of social
fragmentation. In 1848 Engels noted the
isolation of the individual and the
disintegration of society in the great city of
London where it appeared that each individual
pursued his own aims according to his private
principles (Lyon, 1999). Whereas rationality
supposedly liberated individuals from the
authority of tradition, they now found themselves
dominated by the bureaucratic, machine-like
sociopolitical system that was evolving. With
no control over the broader social structures
and practices that affected everyday life,
people withdrew into a private, self-seeking
individualism. In the nineteenth century, de
Tocqueville made the point that although
individualism may protect from certain social
orders it confines people to solitude; in
embracing individualism people withdraw from the
public sphere, which offers opportunity for the
collective control of life (Bellah, Madsen,
Sullivan, Swidler, & Tipton, 1985).
Despite
appearances, ambiguities and ambivalence plagued
modernity from the beginning; and for many, the
Enlightenment promise of freedom through the
development of rationality resulted in
disenchantment. Unintended effects of
modernization became evident, and a cultural
reaction against it was established by the end
of the nineteenth century. By the late twentieth
century heated theoretical debate was creating a
decisive split between those who would still
come to terms with modernity and those who
pronounced a shift to postmodernity.
Postmodern
Debate
Originating
largely in the cultural sphere, the postmodern
debate gained momentum in the 1960s through the
work of such theorists as Foucault, Derrida,
Lyotard, and Baudrillard (Best & Kellner,
1997). Experiencing the advent of new social
movements opposing the Vietnam War, racism,
sexism, and imperialism, they believed that a
decisive break with the past had occurred--that a revolution in morals, politics, and
perceptions was leading to a new era in history.
Opposing holistic views of the world, they
characterized society in terms of fragmentation,
pluralism, and individualism and promoted a
"politics of difference." By the 1970s
postmodern theorists were pointing to a variety
of major social and cultural changes as
indications of the arrival of a new era, e.g.,
rapid growth of new technology and globalization
in addition to new social movements.
By the late
twentieth century two opposing themes had
emerged. First, postmodernism is viewed as
continuous with modernity while challenging and
seeking to redefine it. From this perspective,
there is no break from the past, as certain
things have not changed--although there may be
signs of discontinuity, signs of continuity are
also recognized. Second, there is a complete break
from modernism. Here, there is reference to the
exhaustion or the disintegration of modernity,
or of modernity "digging its own
grave" (Smart, 1993).
A
Crystallization of the Issues
Recognizing the
conceptual complexity of postmodernity, White
(1991) identified four issues on which he
believed ethical-political reflection should focus: increasing incredulity toward metanarratives
(overarching theories), growing awareness of
the costs of societal rationalization, the
explosion of information technologies, and the
emergence of new social movements:
1.
Metanarratives or foundational interpretive
schemes justifying scientific-technological and
political projects came under attack from
Lyotard in 1984. Even earlier, in the late 1940s
there had been critique of overarching schemes
justifying the ideal of the good life stemming
from scientific-technological progress. The
1960s and 1970s brought an unprecedented attack
from feminists on the metanarratives surrounding
male-female relationships. Critiques of
liberalism that arose in the 1970s and 1980s
raised questions of justice, i.e., of the
traditional liberal principle of neutrality or
tolerance of all social groups, although
suppressing or marginalizing difference.
2.
Foucault, Lyotard, and Habermas (who is not
a postmodernist) have reevaluated the costs of societal
rationalization. Among other things, attention
is drawn to the pervasiveness of technical
rationality and to problems associated with
growth of the state's welfare activities. There
is recognition that no matter how benevolent
these activities are meant to be, they often
result in the disempowerment of clients. And
there is a focus on the role of corporate
capitalism in this process.
3.
The explosion of new technology is also a
subject of critique. Although these technologies
are often seen as instruments that empower
people, for some they are "the instrument
of an emerging Big Brother or a potent new
ideological apparatus of corporate
capitalism" (White, 1991, p. 9). Both views
acknowledge that new technologies have enormous
power to structure the ideas and self-identity
of individuals and groups, but they do not agree
upon who will control the technologies and what
purposes they will serve. Although
decentralizing advances in technology may well
provide opportunities for enhanced individual
control over everyday life, much of the
information technology will continue to be
linked to large institutions thereby enhancing
ideological control by dominant groups. It
remains to be seen which
segments of society are systematically
advantaged or disadvantaged.
This raises questions of power, ideology,
freedom, and justice.
4.
New social movements such as the women's
movement, the antinuclear movement, ethnic
movements, homosexuals, environmentalists, and
counterculture groups differ in many ways. But
they all have in common intent of
"defending and restoring endangered ways of
life" (Habermas, 1987, p. 392). They all
focus on the struggle to socially construct
their own collective identity. Celebration
of difference as a value, opposing
consensus and intersubjectivity, is a recurring
theme. The postmodern world is a pluralistic
world in which there are no agreed principles
denying the right of any form of life to exist.
Postmodernity
as Paradox
Paradoxically, no
agreement has been forthcoming on what
constitutes the postmodern or whether we are
indeed experiencing a postmodern era (Best &
Kellner, 1997). Some theorists argue that
contemporary societies with their new
technologies and social, political, and economic
transformations are undergoing such striking
change that we are witnessing the emergence of a
complex period demanding new theories. Yet,
postmodernism rejects coherent theory--it tends
to "patch together disparate objects,
themes, and ideas, with the intent of breaking
up the facade of unity, coherence, and progress
that modernity has attempted to present"
(Trey, 1998, p. 4). Although postmodern theories
could help to throw light on contemporary
realities, whether they are adequate to the task
is open to question.
Analyses of
postmodernity raise ethical questions about
contemporary conditions that point to political
options. Enormous ethical issues to do with, for example,
globalization and the future of the human body
confront the contemporary world.
However, as O'Neill (1995, p. 1) notes, "We
are asked to believe that human beings are now
so speciated by gender and race--though we are
silent about class--that there can be no
universal knowledge, politics, or
morality." Although individuals are faced
with difficult questions, it is evident that
there must be a focus on communicative
rationality and communal ethics. Yet, postmodern
culture would exclude the possibility of this.
Although social
pluralism and diversity are recognized, postmodernists
claim society is not ordered and
integrated according to any principle.
Celebrating the collapse of metatheory that
provided some sense of the coherence of society,
they see no "controlling and directing
force to give it shape and meaning. . . . There is simply a more or less random,
directionless flux across all sectors of
society" (Kumar, 1995, p. 103).
With an
unquestioning belief that we are living in a
postmodern world, we may be inclined to confuse
surface transformations with social reality. For
example, Apple (1996) argued that whereas in
some cases discussion of the need for
educational reforms may have a postmodern
ring, many proposals have little that is
postmodern about them. He argued "they
are often guided by an underlying faith in
technical rationality as the basis for solving
problems" (p. xi). Moreover,
specialization (an outcome of technical
rationality) continues to be a powerful force in
education.
Modern or
Postmodern Assumptions for Family and Consumer
Sciences
Modernity and
postmodernity are concepts that help us to
organize our thinking about complex social
realities. They are concepts that can contribute
to our understanding of social, cultural, and
political conditions impacting family life and
the development of our profession. Although the
modernity/postmodernity discourse is
complicated, controversial, and often heated, it
raises important questions for family and
consumer sciences: Should we hold to modernity's
belief in continued human progress based on the
technical rationality of empirical science?
Should we join those who rage against reason and
rationality?
Should we merely celebrate pluralism, or is
dialogue across difference desirable and
possible?
Should We
Hold to the Beliefs of Modernity?
An increasingly
powerful scientific-technological worldview has
certainly left its mark on the field of family
and consumer sciences (Brown, 1993; Brown &
Baldwin, 1995).
Although earlier aims of home economics were
stated as problem oriented, it could be
expected that the field would be conceptualized
and organized in relation to practical-moral
problems of the family. But in 1913 the AHEA
published a syllabus of home economics
designed according to a job analysis of
household tasks. Content was fragmented
according to the components of food, clothing,
shelter, and household and institution
management (Brown, 1985). Although expressing
concern for problems of family life, home
economists confused household tasks with family
problems. Families do not live in
compartmentalized lives, but in the interest of scientific understanding and
technical efficiency the field
continues to be fragmented and categorized
according to household tasks. Moreover, the
incorporation of fragments of knowledge from the
natural sciences, economics, and technology
resulted in contradictions, conceptual
inadequacies, and ideologies denying any
possibility of a coherent framework to guide
practice.
Specialization
that formed around homemaking tasks continues
to exist presumably in the interest of promoting
technical expertise. Although we may
think that specialization is an inevitable
effect of increasing knowledge, philosopher Mary
Midgley (1991, p. 9) claims that this is not so;
"it is largely a historical accident,
helped on the way by various chance features of
modern life, notably in the way universities are
organized." In effect, specialization
ultimately forces people away from wholeness of
perspective and common ground, and thus we
diverge further and further from each other. As
Midgley points out, although humankind needs
specialization to some extent, it should not be
developed at the expense of opportunity to share
fully in the human experience.
Criticizing public
education for its bits and pieces approach
characterizing scientific method,
Neil Postman (1993) observed that knowledge is
broken down into disciplines, courses, and
subjects; specializations are allocated to
people who are trained in particular
areas of knowledge. It is assumed that the parts
will add up to a coherent whole and that the
whole is merely the sum of its parts. But the
result is a "meaningless hodge-podge of
subjects" without any conceptualization of
what it means to be an educated person, unless
it is a person who has "no commitment and
no point of view but plenty of marketable
skills" (p. 186). There is no "moral,
social, or intellectual center" in the
curriculum. Moreover, in our technicalized
information environment, fragmentation has been
exacerbated by the widespread use of computers
and computer jargon, which promotes a view of
knowledge as simply a pile of loose bits of
information.
Many critics
including Brown (1993) argue that the family has
been disempowered as a result of technical
rationality and strategic action in the public
sphere. Public dialogue concerning social norms
and goals is replaced by the "steering
mechanisms" of money and power (Habermas,
1987). Decision making by technicians is employed in
the interest of efficiency and
maintenance of existing power structures. The
system offers compensation in the form of
commodities for the private consumer. As a
result, "[l]eisure, family life, sexual
relationships and even one's sense of self and
development as a human being become targets of
commodification, as we are presented with new
and more extensive preselected packages of
behavioral, psychological and sexual
scripts" (White, 1988, p. 115). Social
welfare is offered to the less affluent,
supposedly expanding social rights. However, the
vast increase in regulations in the welfare
state results in an extension of law into
people's lives, which, combined with the
intrusion of expert social workers
and administrators, creates a new kind of
dependency. And this "affects the way we
define and norm areas of life such as family
relations, education, old age, as well as
physical and mental health and well-being"
(White, 1988, p. 113).
The pervasiveness
of technical rationality undermines not only the
family but professional practice. Thus, a balanced perspective fostering
moral-communicative rationality should replace this
one-sided modernist worldview. Democratic
participation in public dialogue is central to
the production of social and cultural life, and
ordinary people can be empowered through the
process. Dialogue is also essential for the
development of an integrative, moral, social,
and intellectual center for our field.
Should We
Accept the Arguments of Postmodernists?
Toulmin (1990)
recalls that during the 1960s and 1970s issues
at stake in humanizing modernity were raised in
a public debate about the aims of higher
education and academic research. The concern on
one side was for excellence, while
on the other, relevance. People
supporting excellence believed that institutions
of higher learning should conserve traditional
wisdom and techniques while developing new
knowledge. They emphasized a focus on the
established disciplines for the transmission of
knowledge. People supporting relevance argued
that it was more important to find ways of using
knowledge for the common good--that
"universities should attack the problems of
humanity" (p. 184). If the established
disciplines stood in the way, new
interdisciplinary structures should be developed
to facilitate this task.
Mourad (1997, p.
132) would develop a postmodern university with
disciplines as "networks of particular
inquiries that would always be subject to
change, dissolution and replacement as different
particular inquiries and linkages come into
being and end." Inquiry would not be
"constrained by the disciplinary
plane" but would "move beyond the
disciplines entirely toward other forms of
knowledge." Postmodern research programs
outside the disciplines "would have the
goal of creating intellectually compelling
pursuits of knowledge that are different from
those in the disciplines." A research
program would be developed through an open
campus forum at which a group of thinkers would
come together to pursue "an intellectually
compelling idea" (p. 133). The research
program would be composed of interested
individuals from a diverse group of disciplines;
however, the aim would not be to "make
diverse disciplinary conceptions commensurable
or to synthesize them" (p. 133).
Disciplinary differences would be used as
"points of departure" in the
development of the compelling idea. As Mourad
(p. 136) does not see fragmentation of knowledge
as "an abnormality that needs to be
repaired," and as there seems to be no
concern for coherent theory, a question that
comes to mind is: Would postmodern research
programs merely become a pluralistic hodge-podge
of intellectually compelling ideas?
Embracing
postmodernism, Richards (2000) draws upon
systems theory (which is based on technical
rationality) in comparing modernism and
postmodernism in relation to the evolution of
family and consumer sciences. Yet the employment
of systems theory is contradictory to not only
the postmodern rejection of theory but to
the postmodern rejection of technical
rationality. Furthermore, noting that "[p]ostmodern
thinkers celebrate language above rational
thought" in seeking to understand
sociocultural difference (p. 84), this author
apparently denies the need for communicative
rationality.
Although
postmodernists are supportive of pluralism and
difference, Burbules and Rice (1991, p. 394) are
critical of the postmodernist outlook that
"embraces incommensurability across world
views, not as an unfortunate failure to
establish common meanings and values, but as a
desired state." The celebration of
difference becomes "an exaggerated critique
that any attempt to establish reasonable
and consensual discourse across difference
inevitably involves the imposition of dominant
groups' values, beliefs, and modes of discourse
upon others" (p. 401). Although not
diminishing the significance of difference,
these authors argue that dialogue across
difference is not only possible but crucial
socially and educationally.
Bernstein (1991,
pp. 335-336) also warns against extreme
pluralism. Although encouraged by the breaking
down of boundaries and the emergence of
"new constellations of texts and themes
that cut across disciplines," he argues for
engaged fallibilistic pluralism. This
would mean recognizing our own fallibility and,
while committed to our own ideas, listening to
others "without denying or suppressing the
otherness of the other." Although conflict
and disagreement may be inevitable, our response
is what matters. What is needed is a dialogical
response through which we genuinely seek to
achieve mutual understanding as we work together
as a community of inquirers.
Critics of
modernity continue to emphasize deconstructing
boundaries within and among different
disciplines, and Crabtree sees the need for
dissolution of boundaries between
specializations in family and consumer sciences.
At the 1996 AAFCS Leadership Conference, she
stated,
We have a
tremendous wealth of expertise that encompasses
a broad spectrum of subject matter areas and
specializations. But individual, family,
societal, and economic issues are not neatly
divided into specializations, and thus, most
issues require an integrative, holistic,
interdisciplinary focus, which results in
synergism and . . . a greater impact . . . . (Saunders, 1999, p. 31)
Vincenti (1997,
p. 319) also recognizes the importance of
interdisciplinarity and "diverse modes of
thinking and interacting" and states "home economics has long espoused
interdisciplinary and integrative approaches to
inquiry and problem solving."
Brown (1993)
points out, however, that home
economists have upheld interdisciplinarity as
desirable for ninety years. Although there is
interest in interdisciplinarity and integration of knowledge from specializations in
home economics, "[i]f the claim is made
that home economics is in reality interdisciplinary, this
claim is false" (p. 251). Some
specializations or individual educational or
research programs may have elements of
interdisciplinarity, but although some
professionals may have an interdisciplinary
orientation toward knowledge, to its detriment,
the field remains fragmented. Brown (1993, p.
271) points out that in the strict sense,
interdisciplinarity involves the
"integration of knowledge from two or more
disciplines to create new patterns of knowledge
related to a set of human problems and may
create a new interdisciplinary professional
field."
Brown would
develop a two-level structure for
interdisciplinary study. At one level
participants would seek solutions to a
particular set of problems. Integration would
take place in the minds of participants seeking
to understand and solve problems. (This process
is intersubjective as there is authentic
communication among coinquirers intent upon
developing a shared reality.) At a more abstract
and comprehensive level, interdisciplinary study
would be transdisciplinary and a coherent
theoretical framework would facilitate this
work. Brown (1993, p. 266) is adamant that
. . . the purpose of home economics and the
knowledge relevant to that purpose cannot be
clarified and justified except in a larger (transdisciplinary)
framework. Only then can there be insight into
and rational agreement upon the basic purpose and
problems of concern as well as modes of inquiry
appropriate.
Unlike postmodernists,
Brown sees modernity as an unfinished project
and argues for coherent theory to provide a
comprehensive approach to reason and
rationality.
Should We
Persist with Modernity as an Incomplete Project?
Some theorists
deny that postmodernity represents a new era but
claim that we are in a new situation providing
for a new world view that allows us to look
back, reflect upon, and ask certain questions
about modernity. Aware of the limits of
modernity, these theorists view the postmodern
condition as "modernity emancipated from
false consciousness" (Kumar, 1995, p. 141).
In this sense, a new light is cast upon modernity
allowing us to see it as incomplete--to
recognize the problems that must be dealt with
but also the possibilities for progress in human
affairs.
Condemning
inadequate conceptions of postmodernists that lead to relativism and elimination of the
possibility of social critique, Habermas (1987)
emphasizes the moral importance of continuing
emancipation that began in the Enlightenment. In
other words, the project of modernity should be
completed, not abandoned. Recognizing problems
stemming from enlightenment rationality, he
argues that the problem is not Reason itself but
the prevailing one-sided version of it, i.e.,
the prevalence of instrumental or means-end
reason. The domination of the communicatively
constructed human lifeworld by instrumental
rationality should therefore be a focus of
critique.
Habermas fears
that feelings of disempowerment resulting from
the invasion of instrumental reason into more
and more spheres of life may lead to the rise of
"tribalism" and "identity
politics" (Lyon, 1999). Opposing
postmodernist reinforcement of pluralism and
difference, Habermas would nurture plurality
within speech communities oriented toward shared
understanding. Dialogue is needed to bring about
the formation of new common meanings and a
reconciliation of differences. Barriers to free
and open communication must be dismantled so
that community and social solidarity may be
pursued through moral-practical rationality and
communicative interaction. Postmodernists often
deny the possibility of this, claiming that such
a pursuit threatens to eliminate differences or
to promote domination of one particular
perspective over others. However, as Habermas
and many others including Freire (1984) and
Gadamer (1982) have argued, it is possible to
avoid this threat while working toward
intersubjectivity and common understanding. We
must cope with our differences, and if we are
committed to a democratic form of life we must
make discussions about issues affecting our
well-being more inclusive, not less so.
Although
postmodernists embrace fragmentation,
superficiality, and difference, Habermas argues
for unity, depth, and mutual understanding. He
claims that his theories are not to be confused
with the foundational, totalizing metanarratives
criticized by postmodernists; rather, his
concepts of communicative rationality and
discourse ethics are grounded in the
"network of . . . interactively shaped,
historically situated reason" contained in
the everyday practices of communication (Habermas,
1985, p. 196). Habermas' theories would not
repress particular interests and needs but
further the conceptualization of them.
Implications
for Professional Practice
Although agreeing
that there is a need for interdisciplinarity in
home economics/family and consumer sciences,
Brown (1993, p. 262) would disagree with the
postmodern dismissal of coherent theory.
Pointing out that the field has become
"fragmented, piecemeal, and lacking
coherence as a conglomerate of specialties in
search of a conceptual framework," Brown
insists that "radical transformation of the
organization of knowledge could mean an improved
profession--with specializations--addressing a
real set of human problems." What if we
were to embrace this perspective?
Researchers
in higher education would be involved in the
development of a coherent theoretical framework
that would provide for (a) critique of the
existing society in light of the needs of
individuals and families, and (b) critique of
professional practices within family and
consumer sciences in light of the needs of
individuals and families. As dialectical
theorizing is an essential element of true
interdisciplinarity, dialectical theory that can transcend the disciplines would provide the
conceptual framework. Critical theory is such a
theory (Brown & Baldwin, 1995). Drawing upon
empirical, interpretive, and critical science,
it dissolves artificial academic divisions and
creates new forms of discourse, critique, and
practice. It has two related components: (a) an
explanatory diagnostic component that identifies the roots of problems in the
sociopolitical sphere, and (b) a theory of
action to transform conditions in the interest
of human well-being.
Teachers
would respond by replacing the traditional, banking form of education with
critical pedagogy. A critical approach would
focus on practical-moral problems of the family,
i.e., on questions of what ought to be
done with respect to specific problems. Critical
theory would throw light on the roots of
problems in social conditions. Faculty from
various specializations would contribute to the
dialogue. Practical reasoning would be employed,
i.e., an informal, dialogical process that moves
participants toward agreement on meanings and
norms and consensus on action to be taken in
each concrete case.
Extension
professionals would base their practice on
the methods of social critique and dialogical
problem-solving experienced in higher education.
They would work directly with families and
groups confronted by crisis situations, e.g., a
group of teenagers confronted by peer pressure,
a group of parents unable to meet work and
family commitments in a social environment
indifferent to their needs, or a community group
concerned about homeless families. The critical
practitioner would work with people to uncover
the roots of a particular problem and to decide
upon what should be done to bring about needed
change.
Conclusion
Postmodernity is a
concept that helps us to interpret a set of
phenomena relating to contemporary Western
society. Different interpretations have led to
conflicting views, even as to whether or not we
are experiencing a radical break from the
modern. If we are living in new times we are
also encountering old problems that we should
seek to resolve. Postmodernists focus on
issue-specific critique and are clearer in
stating what they are against rather than what
they are for. Unwilling to commit themselves to
a coherent political-moral theory, they are
unable to argue for any way out of the crisis
situations that they perceive in society.
If we understand
the important lines of continuity between the
modern and the postmodern, we avoid making
exaggerated claims of discontinuity and rupture.
Upholding the view of modernity as an unfinished
project we could embrace a defensible conception
of rationality rather than merely raging against
reason. Critical theory overcomes the problem of
one-sidedness of rationality that emerged
during modernity. Employment of this
critical-dialectical theory would allow us to
understand social problems stemming from
pervasive ideas of modernity (especially those
responsible for the permeation of the human
lifeworld by technical rationality) and to give rationally and morally justifiable
direction to future change within and beyond our
profession.
References
Apple,
M. (1996). Cultural politics and education. New
York: Teachers College Press.
Bellah,
R., Madsen, R., Sullivan, W., Swidler, A., &
Tipton, S. (1985). Habits of the heart. New
York: Harper & Row.
Bernstein,
R. J. (1991). The new constellation: The
ethical-political horizons of modernity/postmodernity.
Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Best,
S., & Kellner, D. (1997). The postmodern
turn. New York, London: Guilford Press.
Brown,
M. M. (1985). Philosophical studies of home
economics in the United States: Our practical
intellectual heritage, Vols. 1 & 2. East
Lansing, MI: College of Human Ecology, Michigan
State University.
Brown,
M. M. (1993). Philosophical studies of home
economics in the United States: Basic ideas by
which home economists understand themselves. East
Lansing, MI: College of Human Ecology, Michigan
State University.
Brown,
M. M., & Baldwin, E. E. (1995). The concept
of theory in home economics: A philosophical
dialogue. East Lansing, MI: Kappa Omicron
Nu.
Burbules,
N. C., & Rice, S. (1991). Dialogue across
differences: Continuing the conversation. Harvard
Educational Review, 61(4), 393-416.
Doll,
W. E., Jr. (1993). A postmodern perspective
on curriculum. New York: Teachers College
Press.
Elkind,
D. (1997). The death of child nature: Education
in the postmodern world. Phi Delta Kappan, 79(3),
241-245.
Freire,
P. (1984). Pedagogy of the oppressed. New
York: Seabury.
Gadamer,
H. G. (1982). Truth and method. New York:
Crossroads.
Habermas,
J. (1985). Questions and counterquestions. In R.
Bernstein (Ed.). Habermas and modernity
(pp. 192-216). Cambridge,
MA: The MIT Press.
Habermas
J. (1987). The theory of communicative
action, Vol. 2: Lifeworld and system: A
critique of functionalist reason. (T.
McCarthy, Trans.). Boston: Beacon.
Habermas,
J. (1997). Modernity: an unfinished project. In
M. P. Passerin d' Entreves & S. Benhabib
(Eds.). Habermas and the unfinished project
of modernity. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Kumar,
K. (1995). From post-industrial to
post-modern society. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lash,
S. (1990). Sociology of postmodernism. London:
Routledge.
Lyon,
D. (1999). Postmodernity (2nd ed.).
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
McLaren,
P. L. (1991). Schooling the postmodern body:
Critical pedagogy and the politics of
enfleshment. In H. Giroux (Ed.), Postmodernism,
feminism and cultural politics (pp. 144-173). New York:
SUNY Press.
Midgley,
M. (1991). Wisdom, information and wonder. London:
Routledge.
Mourad,
R. P., Jr. (1997). Postmodern
interdisciplinarity. The Review of Higher
Education, 20(2), 113-140.
O'Neill,
J. (1995). The poverty of postmodernity. New
York: Routledge.
Postman,
N. (1993). Technopoly: The surrender of
culture to technology. New York: Vintage.
Richards,
V. (2000). The postmodern perspective on home
economics history. Journal of Family and
Consumer Sciences, 92(1) 81-84.
Saunders,
M. E. (1999). A holistic approach to public
policy. Journal of Family and Consumer
Sciences, 91(1), 31.
Smart,
B. (1993). Postmodernity. London:
Routledge.
Stacey,
J. (1996). In the name of the family:
Rethinking family values in the postmodern age. Boston:
Beacon Press.
Toulmin,
S. (1990). Cosmopolis: The hidden agenda of
modernity. New York: The Free Press.
Trey,
G. (1998). Solidarity and difference. New
York: SUNY Press.
Vincenti,
V. B. (1997). Home economics moves into the
twenty-first century. In S. Stage & V.
Vincenti (Eds.), Rethinking home economics (pp.
301-320). Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Weber,
M. (1970). From Max Weber: Essays in
sociology (H. H. Gerth & C. Wright
Mills, Eds.). London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
White,
S. K. (1988). The recent work of Jurgen
Habermas. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
White,
S. K. (1991). Political theory and
postmodernism. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Note:
The author wishes to express appreciation to
Iowa State University for making available
excellent resources for research during Summer,
2000.
For further information about manuscripts:
Via
E-Mail
Dr.
Dorothy I. Mitstifer, Executive Director
Call
for Papers
|